Big Chemical Encyclopedia

Chemical substances, components, reactions, process design ...

Articles Figures Tables About

Statistical nature of quantum mechanics

In the standard theory of quantum mechanics, two kinds of evolution processes are introduced, which are qualitatively different from each other. One is the spontaneous process, which is a reactive (unitary) dynamical process and is described by the Heisenberg or Schrodinger equation in an equivalent manner. The other is the measurement process, which is irreversible and described by the von Neumann projection postulate [26], which is the rigorous mathematical form of the reduction of the wave packet principle. The former process is deterministic and is uniquely described, while the latter process is essentially probabilistic and implies the statistical nature of quantum mechanics. [Pg.47]

One of the most important ramifications of the uncertainty principle is that it brought about a radical change in the philosophy of science. Classical mechanics was deterministic in nature that is to say that if the precise position and momentum of a particle or a collection of particles were known, Nev/ton s laws could be used (at least in principle) to determine all the future behavior of the particle(s). The uncertainty principle, however, tells us that there is an inherent limitation to how accurately we can measure the two quantities simultaneously. Any observation of an extremely small object (one whose wavelength is on the same magnitude or larger than the particle itself) necessarily effects a nonnegligible disturbance to the system, and thereby it influences the results. Einstein never liked the statistical nature of quantum mechanics, saying God does not play dice with the universe. Nonetheless, the quantum mechanical model is a statistical one. [Pg.64]

P( f) represents the probability of finding the system at time f = 0 in the eigenstate ) of p(0). The qirantity P a I, t) = a jrt) is a conditional probability. It represents the probability of the system making a transition from the state > to the state a> dttring the time irrter-val t when the system has been prepared in the state ) at time f = 0. P(pjr) is due to the lack of initial irrfomra-tion, whereas P a jr t) is due to the statistical nature of quantum mechanics. [Pg.255]

Where A F(z) is the free energy at z relative to that at the reactant state minimum zr, and the ensemble average < > is obtained by a quantum mechanical effective potential [15]. Note that the inherent nature of quantum mechanics is at odds with a potential of mean force as a function of a finite reaction coordinate. Nevertheless, the reaction coordinate function z[r] can be evaluated from the path centroids r, first recognized by Feynman and Flibbs as the most classical-like variable in quantum statistical mechanics and later explored by many researchers [14, 15]. [Pg.82]

It is, perhaps, less known that the concepts of complementarity and indeterminacy also arise naturally in the theory of Brownian motion. In fact, position and apparent velocity of a Brownian particle are complementary in the sense of Bohr they are subject to an indeterminacy relation formally similar to that of quantum mechanics, but physically of a different origin. Position and apparent velocity are not conjugate variables in the sense of mechanics. The indeterminacy is due to the statistical character of the apparent velocity, which, incidentally, obeys a non-linear (Burgers ) equation. This is discussed in part I. [Pg.363]

The statistical nature of the quantum theory has troubled several eminent scientists, including Einstein and Schrodinger. They were never able to accept that statistical predictions could be the last word, and searched for a deeper theory that would give precise deterministic predictions, rather that just probabilities. They were unsuccessful, and most physicists now believe that this was inevitable, as some predictions of the quantum theory, which have been verified experimentally, suggest that a completely deterministic theory such as classical mechanics cannot be correct. [Pg.34]

As a young scientist de Broglie had believed that the statistical nature of modern physics masks our ignorance of the underlying reality of the physical world, but for much of his life he also believed that this statistical nature is all that we can know. Toward the end of his life, however, de Broglie turned back toward the views of his youth, favoring causal relationships in place of the accepted probabilistic picture associated with quantum mechanics. see also Planck, Max Schrodinger, Erwin... [Pg.6]

Feb. 20,1844, Vienna, Austria - Sep. 5,1906 in Duino, Austro-Hungarian Empire, now Italy) is justly famous for his invention of statistical mechanics. At different times in his fife he held chairs in theoretical physics at Graz, and in mathematics at Vienna. He also lectured in philosophy. His principal achievement, and the trigger for innumerable vitriolic attacks from the scientific establishment, was his introduction of probability theory into the fundamental laws of physics. This radical program demohshed two centuries of confidence that the fundamental laws of Nature were deterministic. Astonishingly, he also introduced the concept of discrete energy levels more th an thirty years before the development of quantum mechanics. [Pg.54]

When modeling phenomena within porous catalyst particles, one has to describe a number of simultaneous processes (i) multicomponent diffusion of reactants into and out of the pores of the catalyst support, (ii) adsorption of reactants on and desorption of products from catalytic/support surfaces, and (iii) catalytic reaction. A fundamental understanding of catalytic reactions, i.e., cleavage and formation of chemical bonds, can only be achieved with the aid of quantum mechanics and statistical physics. An important subproblem is the description of the porous structure of the support and its optimization with respect to minimum diffusion resistances leading to a higher catalyst performance. Another important subproblem is the nanoscale description of the nature of surfaces, surface phase transitions, and change of the bonds of adsorbed species. [Pg.170]

Following the turbulent developments in classical chaos theory the natural question to ask is whether chaos can occur in quantum mechanics as well. If there is chaos in quantum mechanics, how does one look for it and how does it manifest itself In order to answer this question, we first have to realize that quantum mechanics comes in two layers. There is the statistical clicking of detectors, and there is Schrodinger s probability amplitude -0 whose absolute value squared gives the probability of occurrence of detector clicks. Prom all we know, the clicks occur in a purely random fashion. There simply is no dynamical theory according to which the occurrence of detector clicks can be predicted. This is the nondeterministic element of quantum mechanics so fiercely criticized by some of the most eminent physicists (see Section 1.3 above). The probability amplitude -0 is the deterministic element of quantum mechanics. Therefore it is on the level of the wave function ip and its time evolution that we have to search for quantum deterministic chaos which might be the analogue of classical deterministic chaos. [Pg.25]

In summary, statistical quantum mechanics permits us to derive strictly classical observables (such as the classical specific magnetization operator) by appropriate limit considerations (such as a limit of infinitely many spins in case of the Curie-Weiss model). However, statistical quantum mechanics cannot cope with fuzzy classical observables (for finitely many degrees of freedom) since different decompositions of a thermal state Dp are considered to be equivalent. The introduction of a canonical decomposition of Dp into pure states will give rise to an individual formalism of quantum mechanics in which fuzzy classical observables can be treated in a natural way. [Pg.120]

This expectation value is of quantum mechanical nature. It does not account for the average over all spins, which is purely statistical. Expressing this average by an overbar, the expectation value over the 10 spins in the sample is obtained,... [Pg.46]

In classical mechanics It Is assumed that at each Instant of time a particle is at a definite position x. Review of experiments, however, reveals that each of many measurements of position of Identical particles in identical conditions does not yield the same result. In addition, and more importantly, the result of each measurement is unpredictable. Similar remarks can be made about measurement results of properties, such as energy and momentum, of any system. Close scrutiny of the experimental evidence has ruled out the possibility that the unpredictability of microscopic measurement results are due to either inaccuracies in the prescription of initial conditions or errors in measurement. As a result, it has been concluded that this unpredictability reflects objective characteristics inherent to the nature of matter, and that it can be described only by quantum theory. In this theory, measurement results are predicted probabilistically, namely, with ranges of values and a probability distribution over each range. In constrast to statistics, each set of probabilities of quantum mechanics is associated with a state of matter, including a state of a single particle, and not with a model that describes ignorance or faulty experimentation. [Pg.259]

You can see that the quantum mechanical model does not exactly locate the electron s path, but rather, predicts where it is most likely to be found. Erwin Schrodinger (1887-1961) shook the scientific establishment when he proposed this model in 1926. The most shocking difference was the statistical nature of the quantum mechanical model. According to quantum mechanics, the paths of electrons are not like the paths of baseballs flying through the air or of planets orbiting the Sun, both of which are predictable. For example, we can predict where... [Pg.86]

The partition function is defined in terms of the different possible energies of the individual particles in a system. The developers of statistical thermodynamics derived their equations without an understanding of the quantum theory of nature. But now, we recognize that atomic and molecular behavior is described by quantum mechanics, and our development of statistical thermodynamics must recognize that. It is why we have put off a discussion of statistical thermodynamics until after our treatment of quantum mechanics. [Pg.601]

A statistical model for the UV laser ablation mechanism of polymers has also been proposed [1204]. This model considers the random nature of quantum physical photon absorption. [Pg.424]


See other pages where Statistical nature of quantum mechanics is mentioned: [Pg.78]    [Pg.78]    [Pg.41]    [Pg.237]    [Pg.132]    [Pg.108]    [Pg.57]    [Pg.389]    [Pg.212]    [Pg.142]    [Pg.11]    [Pg.1]    [Pg.449]    [Pg.301]    [Pg.163]    [Pg.328]    [Pg.449]    [Pg.28]    [Pg.12]    [Pg.501]    [Pg.5]    [Pg.1347]    [Pg.8]    [Pg.57]    [Pg.136]    [Pg.212]    [Pg.31]    [Pg.4]    [Pg.171]    [Pg.134]    [Pg.362]    [Pg.33]    [Pg.4]   


SEARCH



Mechanism, nature

Natural mechanism

Quantum nature

Quantum statistical mechanics

Quantum statistics

© 2024 chempedia.info