Big Chemical Encyclopedia

Chemical substances, components, reactions, process design ...

Articles Figures Tables About

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

E. Barnes, On Mendeleev s Predictions Comment on Scerri and Worrall, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A, 36 801-812, 2005 S. Schindler, Use-novel predictions and Mendeleev s Periodic Table Response to Scerri and Worrall, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A, 39 265-269, 2008 D. Harker, On the Predilections for Predictions, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59 429—453, 2008 E. R. Scerri, Response to Barnes Critique of Scerri and Worrall, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 36 813-816, 2005. [Pg.7]

Clericuzio, Antonio. Alchemical theories of matter. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science - Part A 28, no. 2 (Jun 1997) 369-376. [Pg.392]

For details on the benzene problem the reader is referred to the paper of S.G. Brush, Dynamics of theory change in chemistry Part 1. The benzene problem 1865-1945, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30 (1999) 21-79. [Pg.102]

P. Hoyningen-Huene, E. Oberheim and H. Andersen, On Incommensurability, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A, 1996, 27, 131. [Pg.295]

On the importance of these locales, see Mi Gyung Kim, Labor and Mirage Writing the History of Chemistry, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16, 1995, 155-165. [Pg.463]

Yung Sik Kim, Another Look at Robert Boyle s Acceptance of the Mechanical Philosophy Its Limits and its Chemical and Social Contexts, Ambix 38, 1991, 1-10 Alan Chalmers, The Lack of Excellency of Boyle s Mechanical Philosophy, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 24, 1993, 341-364 Sargent, The Diffident Naturalist. [Pg.472]

I am also indebted to Jed Buchwald for encouragement and helpful comments and to Larry Cohen for taking on the manuscript at a relatively early stage. Without their concerted efforts, it would have taken a much longer time to complete this book. Chapters 1 and 2 have been previously published in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science and Science in Context, respectively. I wish to thank Elsevier Science Ltd. and the Cambridge University Press for their permission to include them here. [Pg.612]

See, respectively, J. Rouse, Philosophy of Science and the Persistent Narratives of Modernity) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 22 (1991), pp. 141-62 R. Ulife, Rhetorical Vices Outlines of a Feyerabendian History of Science) History of Science, 30 (1992), pp. 199-219. [Pg.261]

B. Latour, Essay Review Postmodern No, Simply Amodern Steps Towards an Anthropology of Science , Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 21 (1990), pp. 145-71. Golinski, Making Natural Knowledge, p. 30. See S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth Civility and Society in the Seventeenth Century (Chicago, IL University of Chicago Press, 1994). [Pg.285]

De Vidi, D., Solomon, G. 1994. "Geometric Conventionalism and Carnap s Principle of Tolerance." Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 25 773-783. [Pg.182]


See other pages where Studies in History and Philosophy of Science is mentioned: [Pg.46]    [Pg.48]    [Pg.50]    [Pg.52]    [Pg.54]    [Pg.56]    [Pg.58]    [Pg.60]    [Pg.62]    [Pg.64]    [Pg.66]    [Pg.68]    [Pg.70]    [Pg.72]    [Pg.74]    [Pg.76]    [Pg.78]    [Pg.80]    [Pg.82]    [Pg.84]    [Pg.86]    [Pg.88]    [Pg.90]    [Pg.541]    [Pg.271]    [Pg.271]    [Pg.277]    [Pg.287]    [Pg.295]    [Pg.303]    [Pg.307]   


SEARCH



Philosophy

Philosophy of science

Science philosophy

Sciences history

© 2024 chempedia.info